Table of Contents Table of Contents
Previous Page  240 / 464 Next Page
Information
Show Menu
Previous Page 240 / 464 Next Page
Page Background

226

RALPH JANIK

CYIL 6 ȍ2015Ȏ

considerations,

3

just war theory also knew the goals of advancing civilisation and to

wage war in order to spread Christianity.

4

It goes without saying that, as the sovereign ruler who decided upon initiating

war had no superior authority above him and since for some it was at least possible to

imagine a war that was – subjectively and even objectively – just on both sides, the idea

of just war was inherently prone to abuse.

5

Starting with Grotius, who arguably showed

little interest in identifying which side to a war was ‘right’ and ‘wrong’, international

law thus gradually shifted away from this dichotomy,

6

and by the 19

th

century the use

force as

ultima ratio

in order to resolve disputes was perfectly legal, and the question

of righteousness had thus become irrelevant.

7

During the First World War, often

described as the inevitable consequence of this approach, the idea of returning to

the basic assumptions of just war theory gained increasing importance. To many,

the collective security system of the Covenant of the League of Nations embodied

an institutionalization of this idea.

8

And even although the Treaty of Versailles

and the League of Nations system ultimately failed to prevent the Second World

War, the founding fathers once again turned to the idea of institutionalizing and

prohibiting the resort to violence

9

and decided to avoid any legal loophole

10

when

trying to formulate Article 2(4) in the most clear, general and all-encompassing

3

Robert John Auraujo, ‘Our Debt to De Vitoria: A Catholic Foundation of Human Rights’ (2012) 10/2

Ave Maria Law Review

313; Charles H. McKenna, ‘Francisco de Vitoria: Father of International Law’

(1932) 21/84

Irish Quarterly Review

635.

4

See

e.g

, Thomas Alfred Walker,

A History of the Law of Nations

(CUP, 1899), pp. 95-104.

5

See Joachim von Elbe, ‘The Evolution of the Concept of the Just War in International Law’ (1939) 33/4

The American Journal of International Law

665, 674-83.

6

For this decline, see Stephen C. Neff,

War and the Law of Nations. A General History

(CUP, 2005), 95-

102 or C. G. Roelofsen, ‘Grotius and the Development of International Relations Theory: “The Long

Seventeenth Century” and the Elaboration of a European States System (1997) 17

Quinnipiac Law

Review

35, 50-51.

7

See, among the many prominent writers of the late 19

th

and early 20

th

century,

e.g.

Henry Wheaton,

Elements of InternationalLaw

(Little, Brown, and Company, 1866), 368; John Westlake,

International

Law. Part II: War

(CUP, 1913), 1; Franz von Liszt,

Das Völkerrecht. Systematisch dargestellt

(Julius

Springer, 1915), 301; Lassa Oppenheim,

International Law. A Treatise. Volume II, War and Neutrality

(Longmans, Green, and Co, 1906), 55-56.

8

Neff (

supra

n6),290-293and314-317.

Cf.

,however,WilhelmG.Grewe,

Epochen derVölkerrechtsgeschichte

(Nomos, 1984), 788, who describes the two conflicting views on the extent to which the system of

collective security indeed marks a return to Grotius and the idea of just war.

9

As a reminder, the Preamble to the Charter emphasizes the founding fathers’ ambition ‘to save succeeding

generations from the scourge of war, which twice in our lifetime has brought untold sorrow to mankind.’

10

For instance, under the hitherto arguably most crucial and significant step on the prohibition of war,

the 1928 Kellogg-Briand Pact, its parties declared‚ that they condemn recourse to war for the solution

of international controversies‘ and include, and renounce it, as an instrument of national policy in their

relations with one another’ and thus arguably left open the possibility to legally resort to force short of

war; see Derek Bowett,

Self-Defence in International Law

(Manchester University Press, 1958), 136.