Table of Contents Table of Contents
Previous Page  248 / 464 Next Page
Information
Show Menu
Previous Page 248 / 464 Next Page
Page Background

234

RALPH JANIK

CYIL 6 ȍ2015Ȏ

Still, the track record of interventions to restore democracy has shown that these legal

difficulties are more important on a doctrinal than on a practical level. Proponents of

democratic interventionism may have achieved a partial victory for the time being.

6. The Intermarriage Between Pro-democratic Intervention,

Humanitarian Intervention, and the Responsibility to Protect

From the discussion above we may draw two preliminary conclusions which

have significant implications for those that are unsatisfied with the law as it stands.

First of all, the international community seems to have raised a conceptual wall

between intervention in the name of human rights and regime change. Hence, any

intervention of the former kind is suspected as being abusive if it involves domestic

overhaul, regardless of whether as a by-product or an intended outcome.

60

Conceptually, however, intervention for humanitarian purposes, be it under the

banner of humanitarian intervention or the responsibility to protect, is inherently

connected with the idea of pro-democratic intervention. Both proceed from the

premise that sovereignty is not an end in itself but conditional upon a certain quality

of relationship between the state/the government and its people. If this requirement is

not satisfied, a state’s sovereignty may be overruled – it is not far from taking military

action to prevent a regime from using force against its own people to end its rule

altogether. After all, a regime that perpetrates human rights violations that warrant

military intervention can also be said to have forfeited its legitimacy to such an extent

that it is due to be overthrown. Going even further, such a regime never possessed any

legitimacy in the first place – the perpetration of human rights violations would thus

only constitute an occasion to topple a government that could have been overthrown

ever since it came to power. In other words: an oppressive government by itself

provides for a just cause and the changed attitude of other states in light of massacres

against the civilian population has had an impact on another requirement of just

wars, namely the prospect for success. It is for this very reason that many states are so

sceptical about the concept of humanitarian intervention. For, by its very nature, it

essentially implies the possibility, often even the need of regime change.

For this very reason, proponents of just war theory usually do not only argue in

favour of humanitarian intervention but also endorse the idea of forcible democratization.

Fernando Tesón, one of the fiercest proponents of the expansive view on military

interventions in the name of human rights, for instance, explicitly established a link

between these two causes for war. Already in his seminal

A Philosophy of International

Law

, he described the party to any given conflict that resorts to violence in order to

(eds.) Democratic Governance and International Law (CUP,2000) 328.

Cf.

David Wippmann, Treaty-

Based Intervention: Who Can Say No?’ (1995) 62/2

University of Chicago Law Review

607.

60

See, among the countless examples,

e.g.

the statement of the Indian representative to the United

Nations in the wake of the fall of Gaddafi’s regime, R2P selectively used for regime change: India,

http://zeenews.india.com/news/nation/r2p-selectively-used-for-regime-change-india_759913.html.