Table of Contents Table of Contents
Previous Page  260 / 464 Next Page
Information
Show Menu
Previous Page 260 / 464 Next Page
Page Background

246

PAVEL BUREŠ

CYIL 6 ȍ2015Ȏ

Biologically, the process of procreation can be started and realized only by two

members

48

of society of opposite sex.

49

While procreation is biologically more attached

to women, procreative rights cover both sexes. However, the biological difference is

mirrored also in human rights international norms, where women are considered

as vulnerable persons with respect to their reproductive quality. This is explicitly

mentioned in the CEDAW Convention Art. 12

50

and the General Comments No.14

to the ICESCR on Art. 12 of the Covenant – the right to the highest attainable

standard of health.

51

This difference has also been confirmed by the approach of

the ECtHR. In the Evans case,

52

the Court held that a frozen embryo can be used

only if both parties (partners) consent. Its judgment was based especially on a non-

discriminatory approach to both partners with regard to their decisions to become

a parent in the genetic sense.

53

On the other hand, for example in the case of home

birth issues, only women’s reproductive rights are taken into consideration.

54

In this article, focus is directed especially to the very character of reproductive

rights and their interconnection with the concept of human dignity. Thus, we are

focusing on procreation and issues related directly to it, and we are skipping soft

matters concerned with e.g. reproductive health education. In this regard, procreative

(or the hard core of reproductive) rights are strictly linked to three basic human rights,

what we can call bearing rights – the right to life, the prohibition of torture and

inhuman and degrading treatment and the right to family private life. Concerning

48

In the case of artificial reproductive techniques and surrogacy particularly, it is difficult to comprehend

the question of whether to count the surrogate mother (to this two members) or to exclude her, as she

is only a “surrogate mother” – what the French people call mère porteuse – carrying mother.

49

The term

gender

was previously used in this context. Nowadays it has acquired a quite new meaning.

50

Access to health care services, including family planning, appropriate services in connection with

pregnancy, confinement and the post-natal period, granting free services where necessary, as well

as adequate nutrition during pregnancy and lactation. The CEDAW Art. 12 was clarified by the

Committee EDAW in its General Recommendation No. 24 (20th session, 1999) on women and health

issues.

51

See: ICESCR, GC n°14, E/C.12/2000/4, 11 August 2000, para. 21. … Promotion of women’s right

to health; Policies to provide access to a full range of high quality and affordable health care, including

sexual and reproductive services; The realization of women’s right to health requires the removal of all

barriers interfering with access to health services, education and information, including in the area of

sexual and reproductive health. It is also important to undertake preventive, promotive and remedial

action to shield women from the impact of harmful traditional cultural practices and norms that deny

them their full reproductive rights.

52

Grand Chamber judgment in Evans v. United Kingdom, (Application no. 6339/05), 10 April 2007,

paras. 83-92.

53

In more detail, Cohen speaks about a bundle of rights, differentiating the right not to be a genetic

parent, the right not to be a legal parent, and the right not to be a gestational parent. See COHEN,

Glenn. The Constitution and the Rights Not to Procreate. Harvard Public LawWorking Paper No. 08-

30 p. 1135-1196.

54

If in these issues, it seems to be very logical, if we compare frozen embryo cases, on one hand, and

abortion cases on the other, the logic is less understandable.