Table of Contents Table of Contents
Previous Page  243 / 536 Next Page
Information
Show Menu
Previous Page 243 / 536 Next Page
Page Background

229

CYIL 7 ȍ2016Ȏ

THE USE OF HUMAN SHIELDS AND THE PRINCIPLE OF PROPORTIONALITY…

to protect civilians. Instead, the attacker is still obligated to only take the usual

reasonable precautions to avoid civilian casualties.

That view of the customary international law certainly mirrors that which was

included in the Fourth Hague Convention of 1907.

29

However, the convention

was codified over 100 years ago, and certainly the state practice of modern days has

greatly changed since then. The overwhelming amount of state practice shows that

view as too tolerant of collateral damages.

30

That is not to say that those two mirror

each other fully. Galvin in his research was unable to find a consensus regarding the

scope of the principle of proportionality in customary law.

31

Similarly, during the

NATO operations in Yugoslavia the participating states did not agree in how the

principle of proportionality acts, which caused, for example, Canadian pilots not to

be assigned to US wingmen despite the fact that the two forces had been training

together.

32

The exactness of the principle of proportionality might still lack clarity,

but the drastic version arising from Fourth Hague Convention is clearly too lenient.

3. Human shields and the proportionality principle – a variety

of approaches

The principle of proportionality, as codified, is relatively vague and lacks the

specifics on how it deals with the issues regarding human shields. The question is

that of what effect do the human shields actually then have on the proportionality

principle? Three approaches have been nominated in academia. The contractual

model gives most leeway for military commanders to use their discretion, arguing

that human shields should be ignored in proportionality considerations. The

compromising model argues that, while the human shields must be taken into

account in proportionality considerations, their value can be deducted, and

therefore it allows higher collateral damages in situations where human shields are

being used. Lastly, the human rights model is the strictest approach, claiming that

the fact that civilians are human shields has no legal relevance to proportionality

considerations and must be counted fully in targeting decisions.

29

CHRISTOPHER B. PUCKETT, “Is This Era of ‘Smart Weapons,’ Is a State Under an International

Legal Obligation to Use Precision-GuidedTechnology in Armed Conflict?” (2004) 18

Emory International

Law Review

645, 675-676.

30

ADIL AHMAD HAQUE, ‘Off Target: Selection, Precaution, and Proportionality in the DOD Manual’

(2016) 92

International Law Studies

31, 62-63.

31

RICHARD JOHN GALVIN, ‘The ICC Prosecutor, Collateral Damage, and NGOs: Evaluating the

Risk of a Politicized Prosecution’ (2005–2006) 13

U Miami Intl Comp L Rev

1, 23.

32

MICHAEL BYERS,

War Law: Understanding International Law and Armed Conflict

(Grove Press

2007) 123.