Table of Contents Table of Contents
Previous Page  249 / 536 Next Page
Information
Show Menu
Previous Page 249 / 536 Next Page
Page Background

235

CYIL 7 ȍ2016Ȏ

THE USE OF HUMAN SHIELDS AND THE PRINCIPLE OF PROPORTIONALITY…

into account in favour of the attackers in considering the legality of attacks on

those objectives.”

65

Similar remarks can also be found in New Zealand’s military

manual

66

and ICRC’s model manual for law of armed conflict.

67

It is questionable, however, whether the compromising model is just as much

against Article 51(8) as the earlier, contractual model? Civilians are seemingly losing

protection offered to them by the LOAC when their value is deducted. Proponents

of the compromising model argue that the approach is merely a mechanism for

implementing and applying the proportionality principle, and the civilians would

still be under the protection offered to them by Additional Protocol I.

68

But that argument, while semantically clever, is far from convincing. While

the civilians would not indeed be deprived of the general protection of their

civilian status, they do lose some of the protection offered by Additional Protocol I.

While the approach can be seen as a mere “mechanism for interpretation”, if that

mechanism then deprives civilians of their protection, it would breach Article 51(8).

Also, the LOAC does not differentiate between different “classes of civilians”.

69

They are all civilians, and there is nothing to imply that they could be given

different values for the proportionality principle. Similarly, ICTY stated in the

Kupreškić judgment that Article 57, which includes the proportionality principle,

“must be interpreted so as to construct as narrowly as possible the discretionary power

to attack belligerents and, by the same token, so as to expand the protection accorded

to civilians.”

70

The flexibility that the compromising model claims would not follow

the Kupreškić’s ruling of constructing discretionary powers to attack belligerents as

narrowly as possible.

One could argue, however, that the proportionality principle should be flexible

enough to take the use of human shields into considerations. Considering that if it

is too rigid, militaries would be unwilling to follow it, the flexibility could in fact

enhance protection in some cases. To allow enough room for militaries to operate

even in cases of human shields the proportionality barrier could be too high to offer

sufficient protection in situations where the civilians are not shielding the target

and therefore fabricating higher-than-usual levels of collateral damages. On the

other hand, if militaries are allowed to take into consideration the use of human

shields, the proportionality barrier for “cleaner” conflicts would be sufficiently high.

Perhaps the LOAC should not require more than the states can abide by.

65

United Kingdom Ministry of Defence,

The Joint Service Manual of the Law of Armed Conflict

(JSP 383,

The Joint Doctrine and Concepts Centre 2004) 2.7.2.

66

JEAN-MARIE HENCKAERTS & LOUISE DOSWALD-BECK,

Customary International Humanitarian

Law

Volume II: Practice (International Committee of the Red Cross 2005) 2288.

67

MICHAEL N SCHMITT (n 1) 51.

68

Ibid

., 53; AMNON RUBINSTEIN & YANIV ROZNAI (n 61) 121.

69

IAN HENDERSON (n 8) 214-215.

70

Prosecutor v Kupreškić et al. (Judgment) IT-95-16-T (14 January 2000) 252.