Table of Contents Table of Contents
Previous Page  348 / 532 Next Page
Information
Show Menu
Previous Page 348 / 532 Next Page
Page Background

332

ONDŘEJ SVAČEK

CYIL 5 ȍ2014Ȏ

scholars as (

a

) interpretative, (

b

) normative conflict-solving and (

c

) norm-generating

(gap-filling).

16

The first approach is the most conservative one. It limits the role of

human rights to a mere interpretative guideline. This position was famously outlined

by the ACH in the

Lubanga

case in following words: “Human rights underpin

the Statute; every aspect of it […] Its provisions must be interpreted and more

importantly applied in accordance with internationally recognized human rights.”

17

The conservative approach presupposes a pre-existence of applicable rule under

Article 21(1)(a)-(c). To put this differently, human rights can enter the floor of the

ICC only after a relevant applicable law has been identified.

18

One has to logically ask what hierarchy exists between norms applicable by the

Court? The Rome Statute draws a clear hierarchy between primary (Statute, Elements

of Crimes, Rules of Procedure and Evidence), secondary (applicable treaties and the

principles and rules of international law) and tertiary sources (general principles

of law derived from national laws).

19

The scholars present unsurprisingly opposite

opinions on the hierarchy between human rights and law applicable according to

Article 21(1)(a)-(c) of the ICC Statute. According to

Gallant

,

Hafner

and

Binder

, in

cases of possible contradiction the ICC Statute prevails over human rights, which are

nevertheless superior to other primary, secondary and tertiary sources of law.

20

On

the other hand,

Pellet

strongly advocates precedence of human rights over all other

applicable rules, including the Rome Statute itself – with respect to the role attached

to human rights, he speaks about “international super-legality”.

21

Pellet

asserts

that the ICC is obliged to refuse to apply the Rome Statute (and other applicable

rules) when they are inconsistent with internationally recognized human rights.

22

Importantly, any possible normative conflict concerns applicability, i.e. not validity

of conflicting rules – the ICC is not endowed with power to invalidate a provision

of the Rome Statute (and other applicable rules) which is found incompatible with

human rights.

23

16

Young, R.:

supra

note 2, pp. 199-201, Sheppard, D.:

supra

note 2, pp. 58-63, Pellet, A.:

supra

note 2,

pp. 1079-1081, Hafner, G., Binder, Ch.:

supra

note 2, pp. 173-177.

17

The Prosecutor v. Lubanga

. ICC-01/04-01/06-772

.

Judgment on the Appeal of Mr. Thomas Lubanga

Dyilo against the Decision on the Defence Challenge to the Jurisdiction of the Court pursuant to

article 19 (2) (a) of the Statute of 3 October 2006. ACH, 14 December 2006, § 37.

18

The Prosecutor v. Lubanga

. ICC-01/04-01/06-679. Decision on the Practices of Witness Familiarisation

and Witness Proofing. TCH 1, 8 November 2006, § 10. This approach has been strongly advocated

by part of scholars who at the same time rejected a more generous norm-generating function of

Article 21(3). Compare Young, R.:

supra

note 2, p. 201.

Young

argues that the conservative approach

was confirmed by the Appeals Chamber. Nevertheless, the Appeals Chamber has in the same decision

(ICC-01/04-01/06-772) adopted a more liberal line of reasoning (compare

infra

note 30).

19

BITTI, Gilbert. Article 21 of the Statute of the International Criminal Court and the treatment of

sources of law in the jurisprudence of the ICC. In: STAHN, Carsten, SLUITER, Göran.

The Emerging

Practice of the International Criminal Court

. Leiden: Martinus Nijhoff, 2009, pp. 285-304.

20

Gallant, K. S.:

supra

note 2, pp. 702-703, Hafner, G., Binder, Ch.:

supra

note 2, p. 190.

21

Pellet, A.:

supra

note 2, p. 1079.

22

CASSESE, Antonio

et al. Cassese’s International Criminal Law

. Oxford: OUP, 2013, p. 11.

23

SLUITER, Göran

et al.

International Criminal Procedure: Principles and Rules

. Oxford: OUP, 2013, p. 83.