Previous Page  132 / 346 Next Page
Information
Show Menu
Previous Page 132 / 346 Next Page
Page Background

GAZETTE

JULY/AUGUST

1983

from the perspective of critical moral philosophy involved

in constitutional analysis. Thirdly, the

O Callaghan

2

premise resists an attempt to collapse the distinction

between criminal punishment and civil commitment. In a

criminal case, the subjective approach does not employ all

the factors relevant to the mental composition that might

suggest future dangerousness. The judicial process focuses

on a definite quality — the offender's intent — associated

with a past occurrence. Without an awareness of this

attribute the court would be incapable of framing conclu-

sions as to the harm-producing potential of the conduct,

the blameworthiness of the offender, nor even the

magnitude of the harm caused to the victim. Accordingly,

the very factors that compelled the Supreme Court to

question preventive detention in

O'Callaghan

would make

it morally troublesome to eschew the concern with subjec-

tive intention.

Conclusion

This article is not intended to suggest that correct

principles of criminal justice emerge full-blown from the

Constitution. It is common sense that constructive

analysis of constitutional principles in the domain of

criminal justice begins

in medias res.

For example, we

adhere to many important carryovers from common law

doctrine.

w

However, my stance has been that all elements

of our system of criminal justice must be evaluated in the

light of basic constitutional values. Central values are the

freedom and dignity of the individual as a morally autono-

mous personality. Implicit in this is the view that those

who assert that the Constitution should be kept off-limits in

a review of the criminal process have matters askew.

Recently, attacks have been directed at the constitutional

constraints on police powers on the basis that they

diminish the efficiency of the criminal law and its enforce-

ment.

40

Disregarding the point that that is precisely what

the Constitution is designed to do, the critics also fail to

take the moral philosophy of

O'Callaghan

seriously. And,

as I have attempted to show, the moral perspective

operative in that case governs the legislative power with

regard to the definition of crime. •

Footnotes

M wish to thank Raymond Byrne, BCL, LLM, Barristcr-at-Law, who

contributed to my understanding of the matters considered in this article.

I, of course, am solely responsible for its faults.

1. See J. M. Kellv,

The Irish Constitution

, pp. 286 IT.

2. [1966| I.R. 501.

3.

IhiJ.,

at 513-4.

4.

IN J.,

at 508-9.

5.

Ibid.,

at 513 (emphasis is added).

6. Laurcncc H. Tribe, "An Ounce of Detention: Preventive Justice in

the World of John Mitchell", (1970) 56 l'a. I.. Rev. 371, 404.

7.

Ibid.

, at p. 379.

8. [1966] I.R. 501, 517.

9. In our legal system the principle has been regarded as a more or less

self-evident requirement of justice: scc/LG.

r. Cunningham

[1932|

I .R. 28, where O'Byrne J. declared that the court "must have regard

to the fundamental doctrine recognised in the courts that the crimi-

nal law must be certain and specific, and that no person is to be

punished unless and until he has been convicted of an offence recog-

nised bv law a£ a crime and punishable as such". See also

The People

v. Edge

[1943] I.R. 125.

10. Unreported, High Court (McWilliam J ), 24 October 1

-9/8;

and

unreported, Supreme Court, 31 July 1980.

II. As amended and applied in Ireland by the Prevention of Crimes Act,

1871, and the Penal Servitude Act, 1891.

12. At p. 12 McWilliam J.'s judgment.

13. The majority invalidated three of the claimants' convictions.

McWilliam J. had invalidated two.

14. At pp. 7 and 8 of Hency J.'s judgment (Griffin and Parke JJ. con-

curring).

15. See

The Moralitv of Law

(1964) p. 53.

16. 283 U.S. 25, 27 (1931).

17. See,

e.g., People v. Murray

[1977] I.R. 368 (homicide);

People v.

MacEoin

[ 1978] I.R. 365 (manslaughter) and

People v. Dwver

[1972

I.R. 416 (self-defence).

18. H.L.A. Hart,

Punishment and Responsibility,

(Oxford, 1968) p. 182

19.

Ibid.,

at p. 140; see also the judgment of Stephen J. in

R. v. Tolsot.

(1889) 23 Q.B.D. 168.

20.

Ibid.,

at p. 147.

21.

Ibid.,

at pp. 150-151.

22. An example of an excuse is the defence of insanity. Self-defence is an

example of a justification.

23. See Barbara Wooton,

Social Science and Social Pathologv,

esp. Ch.

VIII.

24. Hart,

Punishment and Responsibility,

p. 181.

25. See

Doyle v. Wicklow County Council

[1974] I.R. 55. See also R. J.

O'Hanlon,

"Not Guilty Because

of

Insanity"

3 /r.

Jur.

(N.S.)

61. In

The People (Attorney General) v. Hayes

(Central Criminal Court, 30

November 1967), Henchy J., noting that "legal sanity does not

necessarily coincide with what medical men would call insanity",

said "but if it is open to the jury to say, as say they must, on the

evidence, that this man understood the nature and quality of his act,

and understood its wrongfulness, morally and legally, but that

nevertheless he was debarred from refraining from assaulting his

wife fatally because of a defect of reason, due to his illness, it seems to

me that it would be unjust, in the circumstances of this case not to

allow the jury to consider the case on these grounds".

26.

State (Heah) v. Donoghue

[1976| I.R. 325, 353.

27. In

Melling V. O Mathgamhna

[1962| I.R. 1, at 48.

28. [1963) I.R. 170.

29.

Ibid.,

at 182-183.

30.

Ibid.,

at 182-183.

31. See Cesare Beccaria,

An Essay on Crimes and Punishment

26 (London

1767).

32. See George Fletcher,

Rethinking Criminal Law

(Boston 1978).

33.

Ibid.,

at pp. 115-116. Fletcher argues, for example, that "manifest

criminality" requires that larceny be found only where the conduct

"bears the mark of a forcible or stealthful act of thieving" (at p. 86).

34.

Ibid.,

at p. 118.

35.

Ibid.,

at p. 389.

36.

Ibid.,

at p. 120.

37.

Ibid.,

at p. 170.

38.

Ibid.,

at p. 171.

39.

e.g.,

the presumption of innocence.

40. See McLaughlin "Legal Constraints in Criminal Investigation"

(1981) XVI

Ir. Jur. (NS)

217.

Safeguard

ISm Business

'Hr Systems

SAFEGUARD SYSTEMS IRELAND LTD.

LUCAN, CO. DUBLIN

Telephone 01-282904/5.

Full provision for V.A.T.

The Alternative to

the Computer

A Safeguard Solicitors Accounting System in-

corporating our unique Cheque Application

will give you instant Book-keeping with full

arithmetic control. Please write or phone for

our free accounting manual and further infor-

mation without, of course, any obligation.

Comp l i es fully with the Solicitors'

Accounts Regulations.

124