Table of Contents Table of Contents
Previous Page  162 / 350 Next Page
Information
Show Menu
Previous Page 162 / 350 Next Page
Page Background

LUDOVICA POLI

CYIL 4 ȍ2013Ȏ

issue of such protection has not been resolved within the majority of the contracting

states themselves” and, on the other, that “there [was] no European consensus on the

scientific and legal definition of the beginning of life”.

22

The identification of a gradation in the procreation process, detectable in the

Costa and Pavan

judgment, does not completely alter the stance of the Court as to

the question of the beginning of life, which still remains not completely answered.

Nonetheless, the Court went so far as to deal with an issue that it had previously

considered with extreme carefulness, not just when the question was strictly related

to the protection of the mother’s rights, but also when the circumstances of the case,

as in

Vo

v.

France

, did not require a balance between the rights of an unborn child and

those pertaining to a third subject.

IV. Limiting Eugenics Concerns: a Pioneering Role for the ECtHR

Another relevant element of the judgment in

Costa and Pavan

is represented by

the stance adopted by the judges with reference to the alleged eugenic nature of the

PID. The ECtHR, being a pioneer in addressing this issue, made it clear that PID

does not necessarily involve perverse eugenic applications.

New scientific possibilities of PID have resulted in a shift from “traditional”

application of eugenics (

i.e.

, projects for the improvement of the human race based

on the selection by the State of who can procreate), as they modify both who is

responsible for and the victims of eugenic intervention.

23

Future parents are now in

a position to know in advance the genetic makeup of their children: therefore, their

specific aspirations as to their offspring’s characteristics can (at least potentially) be

satisfied. From this perspective, PID can transform parents from “victims” of a State’s

impositions to being “responsible” for a choice that is inflicted on their potential

children.

24

For these reasons, undoubtedly, PID deserves special attention from a human

rights perspective. Nevertheless, for the time being, no international law document

distinguishes between possible different forms of “contemporary” eugenics: from

a purely “negative” one (aimed at preventing the implantation of embryos presenting

serious genetic diseases), to various forms of ‘positive’ eugenics, such as allowing

the parents to select an embryo with specific genetic features meeting their liking

or, which would permit the use organic materials of the embryo itself (or the child,

once born) to treat a living brother affected by a serious disease.

25

No indication,

in particular, comes from the most significant instrument on the relation between

Rosenfeld and András Sajó (Eds),

The Oxford handbook of comparative constitutional law

(Oxford

University Press 2012), p. 1142.

22

ECtHR Grand Chamber,

Vo

v.

France

(2004) 82. For a comment, see Tanya Goldman, ‘Vo v. France

and fetal rights: the decision not to decide’ (2005)

Harvard Human Rights Journal

277, 279.

23

Cristina Campiglio,‘Eugenetica e diritto internazionale’ in Nerina Boschiero (Ed),

Ordine internazionale

e valori etici: VIII Convegno, Verona, 26-27 giugno 2003

(Editoriale Scientifica 2004) 453, 461.

24

ibid.

25

ibid.