GAZETTE
j
right to die without futile or unwanted
! medical intervention. The right to
privacy was first located in the
Í Constitution by the Supreme Court in
Norris v AG".
O'Higgins CJ and
McCarthy J postulated it as "a right to
I be let alone" echoing the US Supreme
| Court in a line of cases on the issue.
Whilst all five judges recognised the
right to privacy in the Constitution, the
majority held that it did not cover the
plaintiff as he wished to participate in
conduct which was morally wrong,
thus going beyond the parameters of a
right to privacy which they proclaimed
' was not absolute. In a dissenting
1
judgment, Henchy J pointed out that
| the right may be claimed
"for purposes not always necessarily
moral or commendable, but meriting
recognition in circumstances which
I do not endanger considerations such
as State security, public order or
morality, or other essential
j
components of the common good."
Whether a patient's or their family's
wish to cease medical treatment could
be considered contrary to the common
I good remains to be seen. It would
appear from US and UK caselaw that,
depending on the circumstances,
permitting withdrawal of treatment
might not cause legal conflict.
The right to privacy was actually
invoked for the first time in
Kennedy
v
j
Ireland
14
where Hamilton P reiterated
! the Supreme Court's earlier analysis of
j the qualified right to be left alone.
Support for the right to be left alone to
die in peace can be found in his
judgment:
"The nature of the right to privacy
must be such as to ensure the dignity
and freedom of an individual in the
type of society envisaged by the
Constitution, namely, a sovereign,
Í independent and democratic
society."
The Irish courts' reasoning is echoed
in US caselaw.
15
In
Quintan's
case
16
the
Supreme Court of New Jersey decided
that the constitutional right to privacy
encompassed a patient's decision to
decline medical treatment in certain
circumstances which outweighed the
state's interest in preserving life. The
court expressly held that exercise of
this constitutional right did not involve
any breach of the criminal law as
termination of treatment pursuant to a
' right of privacy was by that fact alone
J
lawful; a death resulting from such an
J
act could not be regarded as an
: unlawful one. The same right to
; privacy also placed Mrs Cadura's
right to refuse treatment on a
constitutional level.
17
Writing extrajudicially (in 1986 prior
I to the
Kennedy
decision which
successfully invoked the right to
privacy in the Irish High Court),
having considered the relevant US
i caselaw, Mr Justice Costello said:
"[Tjhere are very powerful
arguments to suggest that the dignity
and autonomy of the human person
(as constitutionally predicated)
require the State to recognise that
í
decisions relating to life and death
are generally speaking ones which a
competent adult should be free to
make without outside restraint and
that this freedom should be regarded
as an aspect of the right to privacy
which should be protected as a
'personal' right by Article 40(3)(1)...
[I]t is highly probable that the courts
would conclude that the duty to
respect the dignity of each
individual which the Constitution
imposes is one which exists as long
as the human person is alive. The
comatose patient would, like the
terminally ill competent patient,
have a correlative constitutional
right to respect. It would seem
reasonable to conclude that inherent
in this right to which both would
have an entitlement would be a right
to die with dignity."
18
| 2.2
The State's Constitutional Duty to
Preserve Life
No constitutional right is unlimited.
The Constitution guarantees the right
to life. The guarantee is in absolute
; terms and that means that the State,
! through its laws or agents, is not
entitled to interfere with that right. The
[ State, under the Constitution,
correspondingly takes on a duty to
uphold the right to life which may
involve protecting it from private
attack. An example might be a duty to
NEWS
JANUARY/FEBRUARY 1995
| legislate to outlaw a suicide manual,
j That duty is far more limited and is
expressed in the Constitution as to
"protect as best it may"
19
.
Í
The interest of the State in preserving
life was discussed by the court in the
Quintan case.
Hughes C.J., in a classic
dictum, said:
"We think that the State's interest
contra
weakens and an individual's
right to privacy grows as the degree
of bodily invasion increases and the
prognosis dims. Ultimately, there
comes a point at which the
individual's rights overcome the
State interest".
20
The principle identified by the court
can be seen in the current medical
j
practice in this jurisdiction. A person
who is terminally ill is entitled to
make a decision that they should not
be given further life support. Where
the patient is unconscious the next-of-
kin, in consultation with their
physician, are entitled to reach the
same decision. The more extreme the
condition in which a patient is to be
: found, the easier it is to resolve a
dilemma in favour of non-treatment.
As life slips away, the interest of the
State in preserving it weakens in
favour of the individual's right to be
left alone. Just as a competent and
conscious patient has the right to
refuse medical treatment, so too has a
terminally ill patient the right to be
protected from an unnatural intrusion
into the course that nature has
chosen for him. The principle
!
j involved requires that the State's
interest in preserving life weakens and <
the individual's right to privacy grows .
í
as the degree of bodily invasion
I
increases and the prognosis for
1
recovery dims.
I 3. FUTILE FEEDING OR
TREATMENT OF A
;
COMATOSE PATIENT
I
1
i
| 3.1 Futile Medical Care
| It was never intended that the medical
profession should administer non-
beneficial care.
21
From this premise
|
emerges the principle that comatose
patients should not be given futile
medical treatment. A proposed
31